DOI

Submissão: 03/04/2020 Aprovação: 03/04/2020 Publicação: 15/04/2020

 

 

Dossiê O Parmênides, de Platão

 

The logical interpretation of Plato's Parmenides in the Middle Platonism

 

A interpretação lógica do Parmênides de Platão no médio platonismo

 

Chiara Bonuglia

Professora de Filosofia na Universidade de Salerno, Salerno, Itália

 chiarabonuglia@gmail.com

 

Abstract: In this paper, I will show some arguments that reinforce the idea that the Parmenides was considered a logical dialogue during the Middle Platonism. I will consider what some authors say, although in different ages, about how the Parmenides of Plato has been read. My aim is also to display that they were in a general accordance: actually, given these concordances, the probability that this work was classified among the logical dialogues becomes much more plausible. The main source for establishing this is represented by Proclus who, in his Commentary on Plato’s Parmenides, discusses about the traditions of interpretation connected with this dialogue, proposing a classification in which is included also the ‘logical way’. On the basis of the analysis of some passages of AlcinousDidaskalikos (ch. 6), and of some references present in Diogenes Laertius’ Vitae Philosophorum (III, 49), and given some indications in Albinus (Isagoge, III, 148, 19 ff., VI, 151, 5-7), it is possible to hypothesize with a certain degree of truth that the Parmenides, for some middleplatonists, in some respects, and more generally for the Middleplatonism, represented an ‘explanatory dialogue’ or ‘expository dialogue’ (ὑφεγηματικός) which contained the indications to learn the logical method, while at the same time providing an example of how to exercise in order to learn it.

Keywords: Parmenides; Middle Platonism; Proclus; Logical interpretation

 

Resumo: Neste artigo, mostrarei alguns argumentos que reforçam a ideia de que o Parmênides foi considerado um diálogo lógico durante o médio platonismo. Vou considerar o que alguns autores dizem, embora em diferentes épocas, sobre como o Parmênides de Platão foi lido. Meu objetivo é também mostrar que eles estiveram em um acordo geral: na verdade, dadas essas concordâncias, a probabilidade de que esta obra tenha sido classificada entre os diálogos lógicos se torna muito mais plausível. A principal fonte para estabelecer isso é representada por Proclo, que, em seu Comentário sobre o Parmênides de Platão, discute as tradições de interpretação relacionadas a este diálogo, propondo uma classificação na qual também está incluído o ‘modo lógico’. Com base na análise de algumas passagens do Didaskalikos de Alcino (cap. 6) e de algumas referências presentes na Vitae Philosophorum de Diógenes Laércio (III, 49), e com algumas indicações em Albino (Isagoge, III, 148, 19 e segs., VI, 151, 5-7), é possível supor com certo grau de verdade que o Parmênides, para alguns médios platonistas, em alguns aspectos, e mais geralmente para o médio platonismo, representava um ‘diálogo explicativo’ ou ‘diálogo expositivo’ (ὑφεγηματικός) que continha as indicações para aprender o método lógico, fornecendo ao mesmo tempo um exemplo de como se exercitar para aprendê-lo.

Palavras-Chave: Parmênides; Médio platonismo; Proclo; Interpretação lógica

 

 

The first commentators who tried to interpret the Parmenides of Plato have understood it as a ‘logical’ dialogue. There are sufficient proofs for establishing that Platonists, particularly the so-called ‘Middleplatonists’, basically read the Parmenides as a dialogue whose content essentially coincided with a logical exercise, or sometimes related to the logic in its strict sense.

In this paper, I will show some arguments that reinforce the idea that the Parmenides was considered a logical dialogue during the Middle Platonism. I will gather these arguments by some authors who, in a more or less explicit manner, show to understand the Parmenides in a logical sense. I will consider what some authors say, although in different ages, about how the Parmenides of Plato has been read. My aim is also to display that they were in a general accordance: actually, given these concordances, the probability that this work was classified among the logical dialogues becomes much more plausible. The main source for establishing this is represented by Proclus who, in his Commentary on Plato’s Parmenides, discusses about the traditions of interpretation connected with this dialogue, proposing a classification in which is included also the ‘logical way’.

Therefore, the most important evidence that leads us to defend the existence of a logical ‘middleplatonic’ tendency, actualized in a specific way of reading of the Parmenides, is traceable in Proclus. In his Commentary to the Parmenides[1], indeed, Proclus informs us about the various readings of the Parmenides of Plato by tracing a brief history of its previous interpretations. In this way, Proclus recognises three lines of understanding the Parmenides: the logical one, the metaphysical one and the theological one. This classification allow us to seriously consider that the exegetical tradition of the Parmenides in the Middle Platonism has been more structured than we get used to think (especially as when we reflect on the Middle Platonism we are used to refer to the Timaeus, or perhaps to the Republic, that certainly have had a more important role among Platonists of Imperial Era). Anyway, taking the cue from the Proclus’ classification, I want to analyse the logical reading of the Parmenides because, as we will see, it is likely that the very logic (and the logical method) has represented the interpretation-key for the reception of the Parmenides in the Middle Platonism.

Going back to Proclus’ Commentary on the Parmenides, we find that the three lines he classified are not well defined and, additionally, Proclus does not include the names of the interpreters. Those who interpreted the Parmenides as a logical dialogue, in addition, disagreed with some aspects. As reported by Proclus[2], someone thought that the Parmenides constituted a reply to Zeno’s book, which contained forty arguments to demonstrate the impossibility of admitting the multiplicity of being. According to these authors, Plato would have formed a sort of method against the Eleatic philosophers, particularly against Zeno, showing how the dialectical method (about which the second part of the Parmenides would show an example) would be superior to that used by Zeno[3]. Such interpretations have been supported by some authors who wanted to affirm the presence in the Parmenides of a refutation (ντιγραφή), or a reaction formulated against the Zenonian discourse and method (namely the Zenonian argument against plurality). According to these anonymous commentators, Plato would have practiced in the Parmenides the same type of ντιγραφή he has experimented in the Menexenus, where Plato imitated the funeral prayer pronounced by Thucydides but outperforming the style of arguments and the clarity of the expression. For the Menexenus would only contain a speech in honour of those who receive state funerals, therefore Plato would not write this dialogue to exhibit a particular philosophical content but only to rivalry against Thucydides, resuming his oration (imitating it), but in such a way that it would turn out to be qualitatively better[4]. For some of these interpreters then, in the Parmenides Plato would be showing an example of this kind of ντιγραφή arguing with Zeno. They grounded this opinion on the certainty that Plato, in the Parmenides, was carrying out a refutation conducted through the use of the logical arguments contained in the second part of the dialogue[5].

According to Proclus, the second ‘trend’ of the logical interpretation of the Parmenides is represented by the ancient commentators who divided the dialogue in three main sections (κεφάλαια): the first one (= Prm. 130a3-135c7): containing apories against the theory of Forms; the second one (= Prm. 135c8-137c3): focusing on the description of the method necessary to grasp the Truths (namely the Ideas); the third and the last one (= Prm. 137c4-166c5): that consists in the exercise of the method presented. Those who did this distinction refused to identify the Parmenides as a controversial dialogue (as did the first group of interpreters), being convinced that the three sections of the dialogue had the purpose of training in the dialectical exercise (σκησις γυμνασίας)[6]. In fact, the hypothesis of the One, as put forth by Parmenides, represents for them an example of the execution of the exercise and would not, instead, constitute its very purpose. In this last case, the hypothesis would play in the Parmenides the same role of the ‘fisherman example’ presented at the beginning of the Sophist in view of the exercise of the method of the diairesis[7]. It would seem, moreover, that not all the supporters of the logical interpretation have identified the γυμνασία with the dialectical method, which, according to some interpreters, would be absent in the Parmenides, recognising in it only the logical gymnastics. Some philosophers, in fact, thought that in the logical exercise contained in the Parmenides, Plato has jointly proposed an anticipation of the technique of argumentation that would be later developed by Aristotle, in Topics (Top. VII 14, 163a37b-13)[8]. In this sense, it appears that Aristotle has been the only one to resume the technique of speeches from the Platonic Parmenides and to propose it, from his point of view, in the Topics[9].

Anyway, the advocates of the idea that the exercise of the Parmenides has to be identified with a simple training useful to develop a discourse technique reject the presence in the Parmenides of the Platonic dialectical method. This rejection stems from the fact that, in the Parmenides, the method proposed by the old Parmenides to the young Socrates, and then carried out with the help of the young Aristotle, would not respect what Plato himself said elsewhere about dialectics. In the Republic, indeed, it is explicitly said that it is not suitable for young people[10], and, in general, the method described in the Parmenides, according to the proponents of this thesis, would not present none of the typical features of Platonic dialectics as presented by Plato, especially in the Republic, in the Phaedrus and in the Sophist[11]. Therefore, the exercise would only coincide with dialectic gymnastics, meaning the latter as the technique of ‘well discuss’.

Since Proclus did not give any name for those who support the various logical interpretations, we cannot understand who he is referring to from time to time, nor we can ascertain when the interpreters mentioned should be placed. C. Steel thinks that the first commentators that found a ‘logical’ dialogue in the Parmenides were probably the philosophers of the first century AD, contemporaries of Thrasyllus, who saw in the Parmenides, especially its second part, a dialectical exercise executed according to the Eleatic method (the Zenonian one)[12]. On the other hand, during the Imperial Era, Platonic philosophers had rediscovered the dogmatic character of Platonic philosophy and were intended to affirm some doctrinal aspects of it after a long period of a widespread ‘aporetic’ reading of Platonic dialogues. It is therefore probable that the philosophers of this era were trying to recognise in the Parmenides a precise doctrinal aspect of Plato. The ‘logical’ aspect (concerning the logic) seems to be the most likely one.

Having established that Proclus fully recognises the presence of a logical interpretation of the Parmenides, in addition to this, there is further evidence that allowing us to delve into the logical aspect of the middleplatonic exegesis of the Parmenides.

In the classification of the platonic dialogues, which we know thanks to Diogenes Laertius’ Vitae Philosophorum and to Albinus’ Eisagoge, it emerges that Plato’s dialogues were basically divided into two groups[13]. We find that, on the one hand, there were the ‘instructive’ or ‘explanatory’ dialogues, ‘φηγητικοί[14], which give instructions on some topics, such as on nature, λόγος, politics or ethics; on the other hand, we find the investigative dialogues, ζητητικοί, which concern with starting a research on a specific issue, often examining the arguments ‘for and against’. These two groups, in turn, have been further split into two kind: the first divided in ‘theoretical’, ‘θεωρηματικοί, which regard physical and logical questions, and in practical dialogues, ‘πρακτικοί, that debate on ethical and political matters[15]. This second group of dialogues were instead divided in the dialogues that served to counteract an opposing thesis (‘γωνιστικοί) and those that permitted the participants in the dialogue (as well as the readers) to exercise themselves in a certain technique (‘γυμναστικοί). Ultimately both the last groups were divided again: the ‘γυμναστικοί into the ‘μαιευτικοί dialogues, whose purpose was to help the interlocutor to bring out (to give birth) his implicit knowledge, such as in the Alcibiades where Socrates helps the young Alcibiades to articulate his vague knowledge; and into the ‘πειραστικοί dialogues, which consisted in verifying the reliability of a thesis, as in the case of the Theaetetus[16]; as last division, the ‘γωνιστικοί were classified in νδεικτικοί, that represented the probative dialogues (for example the Protagoras) and in ‘νατρεπτικοί, that were the aversive’ ones, as was classified the Gorgias. The ensuing diagram summarises these subdivisions:

 

Platonic dialogues

 

ὑφηγητικοί

(λογικοί)

 

      ζητητικοί

θεωρηματικοί

πρακτικοί

        ἀγωνιστικοί

       γυμναστικοί

 

 

 

  ἐνδεικτικοί

ἀνατρεπτικοί

         μαιευτικοί

πειραστικοί

 

According to this subdivision, we would expect the Parmenides to be among the ‘γυμναστικοί dialogues[17], but, as far as we know, it was not so. Diogenes Laertius[18] and Albinus[19] place the Parmenides among the logical dialogues (‘λογικοί) along with the Sophist, the Statesman (or Politicus) and the Cratylus, and, surprisingly, we learn that the logical dialogues are placed in the midst of the φηγητικοί ones. Albinus and Diogenes Laertius, in this way, provide us with an important clue about the way in which the Parmenides was read in the Middle Platonism, a clue showing an interesting albeit partial convergence with the Proclean testimony. Indeed, the Parmenides was part of those Platonic dialogues that gave an instruction on Plato's doctrine and, in the specific case of the Parmenides, the doctrine recognised was about the logic. The Parmenides, therefore, along with the Sophist, the Statesman and the Cratylus, would have contained a logical teaching, providing an instruction on the various (correct) ways of knowing the truth. Most likely, it is for this reason that Alcinous in his Didaskalikos uses the Parmenides precisely to illustrate the Platonic logic (ch. VI). Indeed, Alcinous, an important middleplatonic philosopher, of which we have scarce news but whose ‘Didaskalikos’ (also known as the ‘Handbook of Platonism’) represents a work of extreme importance for the Imperial Platonism, uses not for nothing the Plato’s Parmenides to explain the theory of Aristotelian syllogism as well as of the ‘ten categories’ doctrine. First of all, an important thing to note about Alcinous is that his quotation of some sections of Plato’s Parmenides represents a rarity since we have just two direct references to it during the Middle Platonism (namely the Alcinous’ passages contained in his Didaskalikos and an other one we find in the Platonist Cavenus Taurus, as reported by his pupil Aulus Gellius in the seventh book of his Attic Nights)[20]. Anyway, in chapter six of his work, Alcinous recurs to some sections of the deductive series contained in the logical exercise of the Parmenides. This dialogue, in particular, constituted for Alcinous a repertoire of examples and illustrations for the theory of the syllogism, which, in turn, constitutes one of the branches of the dialectical science. Alcinous points out that for each type of syllogism: categorical, hypothetical and mixed (ο κατηγορικοί; ο ποθετικοί; ο μικτοί), Plato has already provided instances. In the same way, Plato has depicted in the Parmenides the doctrine of the ten categories (Κα μν τς δέκα κατηγορίας ν τε τ Παρμενίδ κα ν λλοις πέδειξεν[21]). All this goes to show that for Alcinous the Parmenides was acknowledged as a logical dialogue.

It can be assumed that Alcinous interpreted the Parmenides in the same manner as Diogenes Laertius and Albinus did, intending for ‘logical’ that it was part of the dialogues φηγητικοί. The Parmenides, therefore, did give instructions on dialectics and in particular on the use of syllogism, which in turn is necessary for the correct use of the λόγος. It is probable that it was for the same reason that Albinus argued that the ‘logical dialogues’ could also be understood as a typology of the ‘investigative dialogues’ (ζητητικοί)[22], to the extent that they would examine a particular issue and that, while practicing in an exercise (namely, a logical ¾ or dialectical ¾ exercise), they would not lose their instructive nature (that is about the logic tout court).

A further indication to understand how the middleplatonic philosophers considered the Parmenides as a logical dialogue is traceable in Galenus. It seems, in fact, that Galenus, who possessed a good knowledge of the logical works of Aristotle, and, more generally, which had a great interest in logic, considered the Parmenides as a logical dialogue of which he composed some πιτομαί, now lost but known by the Arabs[23]. Even Galenus, so, would have seen in the Parmenides a treatise of logic.

Based on the information displayed, it is possible to hypothesize with some confidence that the Parmenides for some middleplatonic authors represented an expository dialogue (φεγητικός) that contained the indications to learn the logical method, while at the same time provides an example of how to practice in order to learn it.

This result allows us to draw some historical-philosophical conclusions also inherent at the history of interpretation of the ancient texts. In fact, it is known that the Parmenides did not play a prominent role during the Middle Platonism. The Timaeus, on the other hand, was the capital text for imperial-era authors who planned to systematize the Platonic thinking and to dogmatize its main aspects. The reason for the absence of direct quotations of the Parmenides in the Middle Platonism is allegedly related to the way in which this dialogue was interpreted. Being understood predominantly as a logical dialogue, meaning logic in its aspect of ‘exercise’ (as training required for a rigorous use of dialectics), and in its properly logical sense (in the narrow sense of the term), this has determined that the Parmenides was not sufficiently suitable to be used in a weighty way for the purpose of making Platonic thinking unitary and systematic. The difficulties that distinguish the Parmenides and that concern both the identification of the theme and the unity of the script have most likely determined the secondary role (though not entirely) of the dialogue in the middleplatonic tradition. The centrality of the Timaeus, on the contrary, could be explained on the basis of the topics that peculiarly mark this work. In fact, it traces the outlines of Platonic ontology and epistemology, reinforced by the cosmological argument. All this guarantees the presence of a wide range of contents required by the endeavour to systematization that the Parmenides, unlike the Timaeus, could not easily provide.

 

References

 

ALCINOUS. The Handbook of Platonism. Translated with an Introduction and Commentary by John Dillon. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993.

ALEXANDER APHRODISIENSIS. In Aristotelis Topicorum libros octo commentaria. WALLIES, M. (ed.). Comm. in Arist. Graeca ii pars ii. Berlin, 1891.

AULUS GELLIUS. The Attic Nights. 3 vols, Translated by J. C. Rolf. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989.

BALTES, M. & DÖRRIE, H. Der Platonismus in der Antike. II. Der hellenistische Rahmen des kaiserzeitlichen Platonismus. Bausteine 36-72: Text, Übersetzung, Kommentar. Stuttgart/Bad-Cannstatt: Frommann/Holzboog, 1990.

DIOGENES LAERTIUS. Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 2 vols, with an English translation by R. D. Hicks. London/New York: William Heinemann/G. B. Putnam’s sons, 1925.

GOURINAT, J.-B. La dialectique des hypothèses contraires dans le Parménide de Platon. In: FATTAL, M. (éd.). La philosophie de Platon. Paris: l’Hartmann, 2001.

LIDDELL, H.-G.; SCOTT, R. & JONES, H. S. (1940).  A GreekEnglish Lexicon, 9th ed., with a Revised Supplement ed. by P.-G.-W. Glare, with the Assistance of A.-A. Thompson. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996.

LUNA, C. & SEGONDS, A.-Ph. [éds.]. Proclus. Commentaire sur le Parménide de Platon, t. I-V [8 vols], Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2007-2013.

MANSFELD, J. Prolegomena. Questions to be Settled Before the Study of an Author, or a Text. Leiden/New York/Koeln: Brill, 1994.

NÜSSER, O.  Albinus Prolog und die Dialogtheorie des Platonismus. Stuttgart: Teubner, 1991.

STEEL, C. Commentaire sur le Parménide de Platon. Traduction de Guillaume de Moerbeke, 2 vols. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1982-1985.

STEEL, C. Proclus et l’interprétationlogique’ du Parménide. In: BENAKIS, L-G. (éd.). Néoplatonism et Philosophie Médiévale, Actes du Colloque international de Corfou 6-8 octobre 1995, Turnhout 1997.

STEEL, C. Une histoire de l’interprétation du Parménide de Platon dans l’antiquité. In: BARBANTI, M. & ROMANO, F. (a cura di). Il Parmenide di Platone e la sua tradizione. Atti del III Colloquio Internazionale del Centro di Ricerca sul Neoplatonismo. Catania: Cuecm, 2002, pp. 11-40.

STEEL, C. Procli In Platonis Parmenidem Commentaria, t. I-III, Oxford Classical Texts. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2007-2009.

TARRANT, H. Thrasyllan Platonism. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press, 1993.

 



[1] Procl. In Prm., 631.11-641.14 (See STEEL, Commentaire sur le Parménide de Platon; Id., Procli In Platonis Parmenidem Commentaria; LUNA & SEGONDS [éd.], Proclus. Commentaire sur le Parménide de Platon.

[2] Procl. In Prm., 631.21-632.27.

[3] On the appropriation by Plato of the Zeno’s method in the Parmenides, see GOURINAT, La dialectique des hypothèses contraires dans le Parménide de Platon, pp. 233-261.

[4] Procl. In Prm., 631.20-631.36: “Καγρ εωθέναι φασν οτοι τν Πλάτωνα ποιεσθαι τς ντιῤῥήσεις τς πρς τος λλους τριχς· κατς μὲν κατ μίμησιν ν κενοι γεγράφασιν, ἐπὶ τ τελειότερον μέντοι προάγοντα τν μίμησιν κατ λλείποντα προστιθέντα τος κείνων λόγοις, σπερ ἀμέλει καὶ πρς Θουκυδίδην γωνιζόμενος τν Μενέξενον ἀπειργάσατο, κατν κε ηθέντα λόγον ἐπὶ τος δημοσία θαπτομένοις ες τατν μὲν κείν καθες, τ δ τάξει τν κεφαλαίων κατ ερέσει τν ἐπιχειρήσεων κατ σαφηνεί τς ρμηνείας πολλ δή τινι τν λόγον το παρ' κείνου γραφέντος εδοκιμώτερον ἀπειργασμένος· τς δ κατ' ναντίωσιν πρς ος γωνίζεται, καθάπερ νταθα πρς τν Ζήνωνα”. See STEEL, Une histoire de l’interprétation du Parménide de Platon dans l’antiquité, pp. 11-40.

[5] Plat. Prm. 137b1-166c.

[6] Procl. In Prm., 634.8-634-17: “Τριν γρ ντων, ς κατ μεγάλα διελθεν, τν ν τ διαλόγ κεφαλαίων, οτω γρ κενοι διαιροσιν, ν ν μέν στι τς περ τν δεν πορίας προτενον, ν δ τν τς μεθόδου σύντομον παράδοσιν ποιούμενον, δι' ς ξιο γυμνάζεσθαι τος τς ληθείας φιλοθεάμονας, ν δ τν μέθοδον ατν ς π παραδείγματος το κατ Παρμενίδην νς γνώριμον περγαζόμενον, πάντα πρς ν βλέπειν τατα, τν τς γυμνασίας τς ν τος λόγοις σκησιν”.

[7] See STEEL, Proclus et l’interprétationlogique’ du Parménide, p. 68.

[8] See also Arist. Top. I, 2, 101a34-36: “πρς δ τς κατ φιλοσοφίαν ἐπιστήμας, τι δυνάμενοι πρς ἀμφότερα διαπορσαι ῥᾷον ν κάστοις κατοψόμεθα τληθές τε κατ ψεδος”. In this passage Aristotle states that when we are able to develop an aporia, arguing in one way and another, we will be even more able to discern the true from the false (κατοψόμεθα τἀλητές) in every arguments. What Aristotle here says could represent an example of the kind of the exercise that some authors recognised in the Parmenides; compare with the passage 136c2-5: “κα τλλα α πρς ατά τε κα πρς λλο τι ν προαιρ εί, άντε ς ν ὑποθ ὑπετίθεσο, ντε ς μὴ ν, ε μέλλεις τελέως γυμνασάμενος κυρίως διόψεσθαι τ ληθές”. In fact, Aristotle also calls the “method” just described as a γυμνασία: which will make it simple to argue on the proposed subject”; see Arist. Top. 101a28-30: “τι μν ον πρς γυμνασίαν χρήσιμος, ξ ατν καταφανές στι·μέθοδον γρ χοντες ῥᾷον περ το προτεθέντος ἐπιχειρεν δυνησόμεθα”. Based on this parallel, the method of the Parmenides would be superior to that one of Aristotle because the latter in the Topics would argue on ἔνδοξα (commonly shared opinions), while Plato in the Parmenides would propose universal rules (καθολικοὶ κανόνες) to reach the truth. For the latter argument, see STEEL, Proclus et l’interprétationlogique’…, p. 72.

[9] A confirmation of this argument would be present in Alexander of Aphrodisias, who, commenting on Aristotle’s Topics and referring to the γυμνασία of which Aristotle speaks, states that the description of this method (‘which will make us able to argue on the proposed subject’) agrees with what Plato writes in the Parmenides in so far as: how bodily exercises made according to a specific technique provide a good constitution to the body, likewise, the exercises in the subjects performed by the soul are made according to a method, giving a good shape to the soul. The good form for the rational soul would correspond to the ability to examine (κριτική) and discover the truth. See Alex. Aphr. In Top. p. 27, 27-31, Wallies (CAG 2.2).

[10] Plat. R. VII 537e-539d.

[11] Procl. In Prm. 648.1-658.30.

[12] See STEEL, Une histoire de l’interprétation du Parménide…, p. 24

[13] See BALTES & DÖRRIE, Der Platonismus in der Antike. II, pp. 48-50; NÜSSER, Albinus Prolog und die Dialogtheorie des Platonismus; TARRANT, Thrasyllan Platonism; MANSFELD, Prolegomena. Questions to be Settled Before the Study of an Author, or a Text, pp. 82-89; STEEL, Une histoire de l’interprétation du Parménide…, pp. 27-28.

[14] The term ‘ὑφηγηματικός’ is the opposite of the term ‘πορητικός’; see LIDDELL; SCOTT & STUART JONES, A GreekEnglish Lexicon.

[15] Diog. Laert. Vit. Phil., III, 49, 3.

[16] See STEEL, Une histoire de l’interprétation du Parménide…, pp. 27-28. See also the reconstruction of M. Baltes, in BALTES & DÖRRIE, Der Platonismus in der Antike.…., II, pp. 513-520.

[17] This is because if we think at the dialectical exercise contained in the Parmenides, it would be natural to link this dialogue to its ‘gymnastic aspect’.

[18] Diog. Laer. Vit. phil. III, 49.

[19] Alb. Prol. III, 148, 19 ff., VI, 151, 5-7. However, it is worthy of note that Albinus himself (in the third chapter) in the classification he makes of Platonic works puts the Parmenides among the ‘λεγκτικοί dialogues. See Alb. Prol. III. 14-15.

[20] Aul. Gell. Noct. att. VII, 5-11.

[21] Alc. Did. 159, 43-44.

[22] Alb. Prol. VI, 151, 5-7. See MANSFELD, Prolegomena. Questions to be Settled…, n. 138.

[23] The Fihrist, composed in the 10th century by the bibliographer Ibn al-Adīm, mentions a compendium of the Parmenides attributed to Galenus, alongside a collection of logical treatises (together with the Cratylus, the Sophist, the Statesman, and the Euthydemus).